Tuesday, July 12, 2022

Are the reals actually well-ordered?

The well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, says that every set can be well-ordered. A set X is well-ordered by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of X has a least element under the ordering.

A strict total order on a set X is a strict partial order on X in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation < on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a,b and c in X:

Not a < a (irreflexive).
If b < c and a < b, then a < c (transitive).
If a =/= b, then a < b or b < a (connected).

Zermelo's approach was to argue that each element of a set could be withdrawn from it sequentially and then, if necessary, put into correspondence with a set controlled by the < relation. That is, the members of X are ranked in accordance with Y, a set of numbers ordered by <.

In the point set (0,1] it is obvious that no smallest number can exist after 0.

That is, limn-->inf. rn = 0. Otherwise, rn --> rn+1. That is a "small number" always implies a yet smaller number. Or see the epsilon-delta proofs.

But then, the same applies to any real, not only 0, that appears in the point set [0,1].

This then means that if there is a smallest set after 0, that set must be empty -- which would violate the well ordering concept. Only if we permit well-ordering to mean that any two members of a set imply a strict ordering, are we out of the woods.

Consider:

x1 < x2 -->
x2 < x3 -->
.
.
.
xn-1 < xn

That is, redefining well-ordering and using ordinary mathematical induction should help.

Of course, it has been argued that the axiom of choice proves well-ordering (in first order logic). I suppose that would mean if we have a set of ever smaller elements, we should be able to pick out one by some metaphysical method and call that the smallest. Rather than go to that length, I prefer a modified definition of well-ordering. In fact, all we really need to say is that any two members of a set of numbers obey the relation <, as in a < b or b < a. That is, ALLx e R(xa < xb or the converse).

Sunday, July 10, 2022

Where are the non-computables
in the binary tree picture of the reals?

 


NOTE. Occasionally, over the years, I have published discussions of the binary tree picture of the reals. This post continues in that vein.
We accept the idea that the set of decimal extensions is bijective with the reals. For convenience, we convert to the base-2 number system, such that the reals are comprhended by the set of binary extensions.

To help us in our intuition, we employ a binary tree with a denumerable infinity of stages/levels. That is, at each level is a set of 2n nodes, or branching points. At level 1, there are 2 nodes...at level 10, 1024 nodes... Every left branch is designated 1 and every right branch 0.

Example: At level 3, we have,
  
  L R L R L R L R
  
  which is equivalent to
  
  1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0
  
  
The complete set of stages corresponds to the set of natural numbers N. The number of nodes in the "final" stage is taken to be 2o.

Hence, we see that every path is well-ordered. (But AC is needed to tell us those distinct paths reach the "bottom" stage.) Now we know from the Goedel and Turing theorems that the cardinality of the computables is ℵo, which is that of N.

It is also evident that every rational is represented as a finite digit string that recurs infinitely often. That is a set of all 0's means 0; a set of all 1's means 1; a finite string of 0's and 1's that is either followed by all 0's or that recurs infinitely often means some rational.

In addition, we have the set of computable irrationals. This means there exists at least one procedure that converts a numerical input into some 1's and-or 0's without ever doing so periodically and that this procedure is infinitely (or indefinitely) recursive, as in f(x) = xnext.

Now each path, up to any finite level, we must construe as a proto-number. All one can prove about any such path one follows is that if we know the algorithm, we can say whether the number is rational or irrational. And, if one does not know the algorithm, all one can say is that -- thus far -- the number is computable, as it can be defined stage by stage. In fact, at any finite level, the path has thus far been computed. So there is really no way to discern a noncomputable from the ordinary perspective.

But if we accept that the power set of N exists, in that case it must be that the "bottom line" point set of 2o "originates" the non-computables.

That could only mean, I suggest, that there must be many digit strings (from the "top" or "our" perspective) followed by an infinity of 0's that are then followed by a "finite" (from "bottom" perspective) string of 0's and 1's.

Such numbers are said to be undefined because their paths vanish as they climb skyward. Their paths all converge to the number 2. But they have vanished "before" coming into our finite range.

I concede such talk is inexact. Our language is unsuited for such conceptualization. Yet, I suggest, that intuitively we can discern that the "bottom up" paths must contain the non-computables, but that we cannot, from "top down" obtain them.

This picture does not suggest much beyond what is already known: that the continuum hypothesis is independent of the axioms of standard set theory.

A way to think about that is to note that the set of the computables K and its complement Kc comprise the reals. And R\K is equinumerous to R.

But we must use AC to "pick out" an arbitrary x ∈ Kc because there is no method in our posession for specifying any x. That is, if we define Kc by its elements, we say Kc is defined such that x is not definable. This is almost an abuse of the usual set notation {x|x ... }, which means that "any element x is defined..." So for Kc we have {x|x is undefinable}. That expression, to me, makes clear why CH is such an elusive beast.

A short proof of the Jordan curve theorem

The following is a proposed proof. Topology's Jordan curve theorem, first proposed in 1887 by Camille Jordan, asserts that an...